New York City, 911 Memorial |
Most moral relativistic students, when pressed, seem to agree that certain moral facts exist. For example, most would concur that It is wrong to rape and torture little girls for fun.
How did my students come to be inconsistent moral relativists? Philosopher Justin McBrayer answers this in "Why Our Children Don't Think There Are Moral Facts" (New York Times, 3/2/15). McBrayer writes:
"What would you say if
you found out that our public schools were teaching children that it
is not true that it’s wrong to kill people for fun or cheat on tests?
Would you be surprised?
I was. As a
philosopher, I already knew that many college-aged students don’t believe in
moral facts. While there are no national surveys quantifying this phenomenon,
philosophy professors with whom I have spoken suggest that the overwhelming
majority of college freshman in their classrooms view moral claims as mere
opinions that are not true or are true only relative to a culture."
Where did this idea come from? While there are academic philosophers who are moral relativists, none of my students are familiar with them (OK, maybe .001% have at least heard of a philosophical moral relativist). McBrayer says this incipient-yet-unreflected-on moral relativism comes from our K-12 educational system.
To demonstrate, when McBrayer visited his son's second grade open house he saw a pair of "troubling" signs hanging over the bulletin board. They read:
Fact: Something that is true about a subject and can be tested or proved.
Opinion: What someone thinks, feels, or believes.
These signs represent the norm, not the exception. McBrayer writes:
"Hoping that this set
of definitions was a one-off mistake, I went home and Googled “fact vs.
opinion.” The definitions I found onlinewere
substantially the same as the one in my son’s classroom. As it turns out, the
Common Core standards used by a majority of K-12 programs in the country
require that students be able to “distinguish among fact, opinion, and reasoned judgment in
a text.” And the Common Core institute provides a helpful page full of links to definitions, lesson plans
and quizzes to ensure that students can tell the difference
between facts and opinions."
The fact-opinion distinction is wrong. Why?
1. The definition of a "fact" associates it with "proof." But this is wrong, since "things can be true even if no one can prove them. For example, it could
be true that there is life elsewhere in the universe even though no one can
prove it. Conversely, many of the things we once “proved” turned out to be
false. For example, many people once thought that the earth was flat. It’s a
mistake to confuse truth (a feature of the world) with proof (a feature of our
mental lives)."
2. Students are taught that claims are either facts or opinions. "But if a fact is something that is true and an opinion is something
that is believed, then many claims will obviously be both." What a person believes can be a fact. I believe George Washington was the first president, and it is a fact that he was the first president.
Working from this false distinction the K-12 educational program places moral value claims as "opinions." Which means, according to the above false distinction, moral value claims are not "facts." So, there are no moral facts. "And if there are no moral facts, then there are no moral truths." By this confused, false reasoning the moral statement It is wrong to rape and torture little girls for fun is only an "opinion" and therefore is not true. So "it should not be a
surprise," says McBrayer, "that there is rampant cheating on college campuses: If we’ve
taught our students for 12 years that there is no fact of the matter as to
whether cheating is wrong, we can’t very well blame them for doing so later on."
My students, and our children, deserve better than this. McBrayer concludes, correctly:
"Our children deserve a
consistent intellectual foundation. Facts are things that are true. Opinions
are things we believe. Some of our beliefs are true. Others are not. Some of
our beliefs are backed by evidence. Others are not. Value claims are like any
other claims: either true or false, evidenced or not. The hard work lies not in
recognizing that at least some moral claims are true but in carefully thinking
through our evidence for which of the many competing moral claims is correct.
That’s a hard thing to do. But we can’t sidestep the responsibilities that come
with being human just because it’s hard.
That would be wrong."